- Apr 22
- 3 min read
In policy studies, rationality is often discussed in the context of the public. The question is whether the wider population can be considered as rational actors. Some scholars say this “rational choice” theory does indeed hold on a nationwide level. In this market based perspective of the public, individuals will always act in their best interest. For example, if there is a government grant available to small businesses in a certain region, under rational choice theory, all of those small businesses will theoretically apply for the grant on their own. Grants can thus be designed purely based on numbers, such as amount of money provided and number of slots available. Other scholars say that rational choice cannot be assumed within the public. They suggest that on aggregate, people’s values and beliefs play just as large of a role as perceived rational benefit. For example, a small business owner who is suspicious of government entities, perhaps due to previous problems with the IRS, may be unwilling to apply for government grants, even if they would benefit greatly from said grants. Here, the idea of rationality within the public lies at the center of one of the large debates in public policy, positivism vs post-positivism. Can we treat policy as a science, or do we have to surrender that individual values and beliefs prevent any sort of quantifiable policy solution.
However, the people being affected by policy are only part of the story. In policy studies, rationality is also critical to understanding the actions of policy makers. The job of policy makers is characterized by the collection and understanding of information. Policy makers must collect information, both through data and personal/stakeholder accounts. Then, after understanding the meaning of this data, they must make decisions based on this information. Herein lies an issue: it's almost impossible for policy makers to know enough information to make the perfect decision. Issues often affect millions of people, each with their own life stories that will respond differently to a specific policy action. Yet, the polls and stakeholder accounts that policy makers have access to are often only a fraction of the total population. So, how can policy makers take decisive action when they cannot be sure of what they are doing? This is where bounded rationality comes into play.
Bounded rationality is different from the traditional assumption of rational choice theory in one key aspect: it takes into account the limits of people’s knowledge and resources. First introduced by Herbert Simon, bounded rationality explains that it is unreasonable to assume that policy makers will always make the utility maximizing decision. This is because making the absolute utility maximizing decision would require the omnipotent knowledge of a god, something that policy makers trapped in the bureaucracy often do not have. So, unable to make perfectly fact based decisions, bounded rationality suggests that policy makers make choices based on feeling. Whether it is creating new educational programs in a low employment neighborhood or opening more soup kitchens during a financial crisis, policy makers will often lean on their “gut-feeling” rather than data.
Through this, bounded rationality is significant because it provides a more realistic model of how policy makers make choices. It views policy makers more like humans and less like robots. Afterall, when an infinite amount of information gets paired with tight timeframes, the analyst cannot expect the policy maker to make the perfect rational decision. Bounded rationality provides the alternative, a perspective where the process of choosing policy is just as normative as the effects of policies themselves. Through bounded rationality, the policy process is not just dependent on the content of the policy, but also upon WHO the policy maker making the decisions is. Since policy making is almost always a cooperative effort, where heuristics intertwine between multiple individuals, things get even more complicated! This doesn’t mean that we should completely discard data based policy making, certainly not. But, it does raise questions about how we can incorporate heuristics measuring and other aspects of bounded rationality into policy analysis.